早稲田政経2011 II
II Read this article and answer the
questions below.
[1] From attacking burglars to jumping red
lights, we are increasingly taking the law into our own hands. But can this be
morally justified? Those who do take the law into their own hands often receive
strong support from the public and the media. The Metropolitan Police
Commissioner has even suggested that victims should be encouraged to fight back
against criminals. Such acts of bravery, he says, "make our society
worthwhile."
[2] Lawlessness is evident elsewhere, too.
A cyclist in central London speeds through a red light, annoying drivers who
have to sit and wait. Yet one of the drivers is seen texting as the bike speeds
off. Meanwhile, a student downloads music files from illegal file-sharing
sites. All of these examples point to ( A ), in which people break the law
unashamedly and even attempt to justify their actions on philosophical
grounds―the law is flawed, the crime is victimless or, simply, everybody else
is doing it, so why shouldn't we? But these claims are much weaker than they
seem, and ask troubling questions about the way we, as citizens, understand the
role of protest, and the respect we should show to laws.
[3] Of course, we are all lawbreakers to a
degree. Most Internet users will accidentally break copyright laws, or not
think too hard about the legality of passing on useful files. Every driver has
broken the speed limit at some time, and many have driven over the alcohol
limit. But such cases are different from deliberately breaking the law and then
claiming you have done nothing wrong.
[4] Many arguments used to justify
lawbreaking are classic examples of "neutralization theory." In the 1950s
American sociologists Gresham Sykes and David Matza used this theory to
categorize the excuses of criminals in ways that are still relevant today. Most
people who break the law, they found, only do so selectively, and ( B ) law,
convention, and morality. Typically they admire traits such as honesty, and
have a capacity for guilty feelings. So neutralization is their way of coming
to terms with their wrongdoing, minimizing feelings of guilt by redefining
their actions.
[5] Sykes and Matza outlined five common
neutralizing excuses. First, there is denial of responsibility, in which the
actor was forced by circumstances ("I couldn't stop my bike at the red
light―it was icy.") Second comes denial of injury ( C ). Third, denial of
the victim ( D ). Fourth is "condemnation of the condemners": those
who condemn the lawbreaking act are accused of themselves being corrupt or
selfish ( E ). Fifth, and finally, you appeal to higher values than those
embodied in the law ("Music should be free to all") But are such
excuses ever philosophically sound?
[6] Take the red light question. Drivers do
cause many more accidents involving cyclists than cyclists do among themselves
( F ).
[7] What of file sharers who know they are
breaking the law? Here almost all the methods of neutralization come into play.
File sharers declare they are forced to act by excessively high prices. More seriously,
they tend to deny causing injury, arguing that downloading is a largely
victimless crime―one where, unlike shoplifting, the original item remains
intact for someone else to buy. Most interestingly, there is often an appeal to
higher values: the idea that culture itself should be free. But are any of these
good arguments? It is true that stealing from a shop and downloading music or
other artistic content are not equivalent, but it doesn't follow that no one is
harmed by the latter. Creative industries still rely on paying creators. In
truth, Internet piracy is not a heroic act of civil disobedience; it is almost
always a self-serving way of avoiding paying for content, just as cyclists
running red lights are keen to get home quickly.
[8] Most people accept that it can be
morally right to break an unjust law―think of Rosa Parks and her refusal to
give up her seat on a racially segregated bus, and of those who joined her by
boycotting the Alabama bus system. Perhaps some of our new social lawbreakers
like to think that they are acting within a tradition of civil disobedience,
ennobled by Henry Thoreau, Gandhi, and Martin Luther King, Jr. But how
plausible is this? The philosopher John Rawls stressed that civil disobedience,
in the tradition of Martin Luther King's famous "Letter from Birmingham
City Jail," is not self-interested, and is always performed in public―for
the good reason that civil disobedience is a form of communication that appeals
to a community's sense of justice. As such, it should always be a last resort,
once legal protests and demonstrations have failed.
[9] This means that downloading a pirated
film you want to watch but can't afford, or ignoring a red light on the way to
work, is not a principled act aimed at producing fairer laws. Smashing a fleeing
intruder's head is not true justice. If cyclists and file sharers want to
change laws, they should find public means of protest. Otherwise, those who
choose self-serving ways of breaking the law will continue to have more in
common with thieves who steal television sets than with Rosa Parks
Source: Prospect (January 27, 2010)
1 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to fill in blank space (A)
(a) a growing interest in acts of bravery
(b) a movement that helps victims of crime
(c) a new age of social lawlessness
(d) a show of support from the public and
the media
(e) a society that is more worthwhile
2 Use six of the eight words below to fill
in blank space (B) in the best way. Indicate your choices for the second,
fourth, and sixth positions.
(a) crime (b) desire (c) does (d) have (e)
little (f) live (g) outside (h) to
3 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to fill in blank space (C)
(a) ("It's too expensive.")
(b) ("My friend did the same ")
(c) ("Nobody was hurt")
(d) ("The doctors couldn't help")
(e) ("The hospital was closed ")
4 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to fill in blank space (D).
(a) ("He deserved it ")
(b) ("I'm sorry ")
(c) ("It wasn't my fault")
(d) ("She said no.")
(e) ("You never know.")
5 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to fill in blank space (E)
(a) ("It doesn't really do any harm.")
(b) ("The music industry is so greedy
anyway.")
(c) ("The police should be doing a
better job.")
(d) ("The public doesn't seem to
care.")
(e) ("We shouldn't rely too much on
technology.")
6 Choose the most suitable order of
sentences from those below to fill in blank space (F).
(a) He, in turn, might prove you are
stealing from your company, but that doesn't excuse his own wrongdoing
(b) His reasoning is an example of the
fourth excuse, in which the victim condemns the condemners.
(c) However, showing the faults of your
accusers is in itself no justification for lawbreaking.
(d) If, for example, a thief stole
something from you, you would naturally condemn him.
(e) This fact has led cycling lobbyist
Chris Peck to say, "The biggest problem for cyclists is bad driving."
7 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to complete the following sentence
The writer suggests that as far as
downloading artistic content like music is concerned,
(a) it allows no one to own a file.
(b) it causes someone to suffer as a
result.
(c) it is basically a victimless crime
(d) it's as bad as stealing from a shop.
(e) it's so common that it shouldn't be a
crime
8 Choose the most suitable answer from
those below to complete the following sentence.
The writer concludes that
(a) activists of the past regarded breaking
the law as unacceptable
(b) civil disobedience is an approach that
is no longer effective in modern society.
(c) downloading copyrighted materials is an
act that can be morally justified
(d) ignoring a red light appeals to a
common sense of justice.
(e) people who object to current laws
should convince others to support their position.
コメント
コメントを投稿